Wonder Club world wonders pyramid logo
×

Reviews for Going to bed with rabbit

 Going to bed with rabbit magazine reviews

The average rating for Going to bed with rabbit based on 2 reviews is 3 stars.has a rating of 3 stars

Review # 1 was written on 2017-01-10 00:00:00
0was given a rating of 3 stars Paul Lubinski
Spinoza And German Enlightenment Spinoza and his impact on Enlightenment are getting renewed attention in philosophical and historical literature. The final volume of Jonathan Israel's trilogy on Spinoza and the Enlightenment, "Democratic Enlightenment: Philosophy, Revolution, and Human Rights, 1750-1790", together with Steven Nadler's new study of Spinoza's Theological-Political Treatise, "A Book Forged in Hell: Spinoza's Scandalous Treatise and the Birth of the Secular Age", prompted me to continue with Spinoza and the Enlightenment by reading "Spinoza's Modernity: Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Heine" (2004) which examines the reception of Spinoza in the works of these three important 18th Century German thinkers. The author, Willi Goetschel is professor of German and philosophy at the University of Toronto, and his book is part of a series, "Studies in German Jewish Cultural History and Literature." This is a detailed, difficult book that considers three German writers whose works are not as familiar to American readers as they might be. Goetschel also offers new insights and direction in understanding Spinoza and what Goetschel sees as his uniquely modernist project. Beginning with the German writer Jacobi, Spinoza has tended to be read through his metaphysics and epistemology as a pantheist and a rationalistic fatalist. Jacobi was a severe critic of Spinoza and wanted philosophy to return to religious and Christian faith rather than reason. Goetschel begins differently with Spinoza. He emphasizes Spinoza's philosophy of affects (emotions) found in the latter three books of the Ethics together with what Goetschel sees as the relations between emotion and reason for Spinoza. Goetschel also places great weight, as do Nadler and Israel, on Spinoza's Theological Political Treatise and its discussion of the relationship between politics and religion. Spinoza's unfinished Political Treatise receives much attention as well. Readers frequently underestimate Spinoza's importance to political philosophy. The result of Goetschel's reading is an interpretation of Spinoza that emphasizes its immanent character and its reworking of the distinction between universal and particular rather than a pantheistic reading of Spinoza. It is a materialistic philosophy with some modern interpretive twists. Spinoza begins neither with metaphysics nor epistemology and works down so to speak but rather thinks in a seamless web in which there is no outside privileged philosophical position. Goetschel, in company with some students of Spinoza, emphasizes the Jewish character of his thought as opposed to seeing him as a "rationalist" thinker following Descartes and a predecessor of Leibniz as he is frequently taught in courses on the history of philosophy. For Goetschel Spinoza's Jewishness captures the nature of modernism and Spinoza's role in developing modernity. The issue lies in the relationship between universalism and particularism. On the one hand, Spinoza taught a philosophy of reason and universalism stressing what was shared and accessible to everyone rather than claimed religious revelations which Spinoza rejected decisively as a source of knowledge and truth. But, Goetschel argues convincingly, Spinoza was a nominalist who approached reason and commonality only through particulars rather than as abstractions of a Platonic or other character. So, for Goetschel, Spinoza spoke for a culture which was universal and recognized the rights of all but which did not try to obliterate differences founded on imagination, tradition and diversity and difference. Spinoza spoke of the reason common to all men in founding a secularly based society while allowing for different imaginative expressions including Judaism and Christianity among others. In the first part of the book, Goetschel offers his account of Spinoza's own writings which emphasizes the Spinoza's conatus, or understanding of the nature of self-realization. He works through Spinoza's understanding or religion and its difference from reason culminating in a discussion of Spinoza's non-contractarian (which distinguishes it from Hobbes) political theory in the Political Treatise. In considering Spinoza's reception in Germany, Goetschel focuses on religion, psychology, and interpretation rather than upon metaphysics. Goetschel also sees Spinoza as fundamental to the issue of Jewish emancipation in Enlightenment Germany. In the second part of his book, Goetschel discusses Spinoza's influence on the thought of Moses Mendelssohn (1729 -- 1786) who attempted the difficult task of combining philosophy with Jewish life. There are some valuable sections in this discussion, as Goetschel discusses Mendelssohn's introduction to Rabbi Manasseh Ben Israel's "Vindication of the Jews." Rabbi Manasseh was one of Spinoza's teachers prior to Spinoza's excommunication from the Jewish community. But the focus of the discussion of Mendelssohn and almost of the book is on Mendelssohn's book "Jerusalem, or on Religious Power and Judaism." Here, Goetschel maintains, Mendelssohn elaborated on Spinoza's Theological Political Treatise. He argued for what Goetschel describes as an "alternative universalism" in which the institutions of a society were secular but religious diversity and practice was encouraged in the spirit of self-realization and particularistic interpretation of tradition. Mendelssohn was a lifelong friend of Gotthold Lessing (1729 -- 1781) who Jacobi, in a breach of confidence, revealed as a Spinozist in his outlook. Goetschel's discussion focuses on what he perceives as an instrumental, pragmatist theory of truth that he finds in Lessing and that he argues derives from Spinoza. He links Lessing prospectively to the American pragmatists, Charles Peirce but also to William James as well. Goetschel offers a detailed reading of Lessing's famous play "Nathan the Wise." He sees this play as more than the plea for tolerance for which it is usually read. The play goes far beyond this, for Goetschel, in its epistemology and view of the value of religious diversity. Goetschel finds the play heavily indebted to Spinoza, as does Johnathan Israel in the book referred to in the first paragraph of this review. Goetschel's treatment of Spinoza in Heinrich Heine (1797 --1856) seems to me comparatively short and rushed. Heine took issue with Hegel by challenging what became for a time a prevailing idealistic reading of Spinoza. Heine also placed Spinoza at the center of modern philosophy rather than on the periphery. Goetschel finds a Spinozistic influence regarding universals and particulars and Jewish interpretation in Heine's late poetry, "Hebrew Melodies". The style of this book is academic and turgid. The erudition in this book is deep and the footnotes are essential. The frequent passages from German texts are given by Goetschel in his own translation and in the original. A reading knowledge of German is valuable in understanding the book. I found the book more valuable for the interpretation Goetschel offers of Spinoza himself than in his readings of Mendelssohn, Lessing and Heine. This is not a book for casual reading. The book will appeal to readers with a serious interest and background in Spinoza and to readers with a broad knowledge of German literature and culture. Robin Friedman
Review # 2 was written on 2016-07-20 00:00:00
0was given a rating of 3 stars Sandy Sam
One way of looking at writers who really appeal us is that they share attitudes that the reader can build on; in a paraphrase of Emerson's, they speak the thoughts that we were not strong enough to bring to fruition. Kant admitted that Rousseau was pivotal to his development, that the latter was one of those thinkers who had indeed brought him out of his dogmatic slumbers. Cassirer asks how this can be so in this case. They were in their own descriptions of themselves polar opposites: Rousseau the wanderer to the end of his life, Kant renown for never leaving his little university town. Kant was known as the 'the clock' in his city for the regularity of his habits, Rousseau threw his watch away so as not be encumbered by schedules. These two thinkers provide images for rigid thought versus unbridled passion. It is perhaps to Kant's credit that he was so touched by an opposing current of thought that he encorporated them so deeply in his own. I believe that the dogma Kant overcame by reading Rousseau was a youthful contempt for any sentiment not educated, intellectual, refined. Rousseau had shown him that the most intellectual society of the time, that of Paris in the 1700's, was a tournament of masks driven by vanity. If there was an ideal to which we should be drawn, it was the precivilized human being with his great personal autonomy. Kant was democratized by Rousseau. The aim of education was not intellectual refinement, it was the possible enhancer of the one attribute that made us human and with which every human being is born: the drive for personal autonomy. One of the remarks made by Cassirer struck me as most appropriate: Rousseau, who had made his mark by lecturing on the vanities of civilization and the decline of happiness within that scene, should have been the one who denounced the optimism in human reason that marked the era, not as it turns out,Voltaire. Instead, Rousseau wrote a response to Voltaire complaining that the latter's pessimism was incapacitating to him;he could not accept it. I myself have found this hard to reconcile with the rest of Rousseau, but I think it might be a respone to one mechanistic attitude being refuted by another in the case of Voltaire. The Enlightenment thinkers were sceptical about tradional authorities and optimistic about disciplined human reason bringing mankind to a new level of well being. Voltaire was just aiming the same scepticsm at a too extreme optimism. Certainly his personal ambitions and basic commitments were in line with the philosophs. Rousseau's were not. Society as it was so arranged necessarily brought unhappiness. Only in literally escaping society by living outside the city could Rousseau hope to pursue the only ambition that mattered: something like the personal freedom that he set up as an ideal with precivilized man. Kant was able to crystallize Rousseau's intense ambition and make it less dependent on the vagaries of Jean-Jacque's own life. In fact, one of Kant's achievemnts might be said to be the clarification of Rousseau's response to Voltaire, that life did have value. Rousseau could never quite take the argument out of the sphere of happiness, and it took Kant to put the capper on Rousseau's reply to Voltaire. Kant wrote in the Critique of Judgment: "It is easy to decide what value life holds for us, if its worth is measured merely by our enjoyments...It is less than nothing; for who would wish to begin life anew under the same conditions or even according to a new self-made plan (but one consistnet with the course of nature)". Cassirer adds "The diminution of happiness can not lessen the the value of existence, for this does not consist in what happens to a person, but in what a person does. Our deeds, not our outward fate, give life its meaning. For Kant this meaning cannot be impaired by any suffering, and no pessimistic argument can touch it. No matter how low we may estimate the value of human existence in terms of what man receives and enjoys, there remains the value that a free personality creates for itself." Accepting this as a truly noble and compelling description of what it means to be a human, perhaps the question remains of how much happiness, basic well-being, must a person have in order to have the time and energy to strive to be a free personality. It occurs to me that it comes as almost an axiom that one hopes for happiness for others more than oneself. I can feel my desire for autonomy but I can only encourage it in others by providing for their basic means of growth.


Click here to write your own review.


Login

  |  

Complaints

  |  

Blog

  |  

Games

  |  

Digital Media

  |  

Souls

  |  

Obituary

  |  

Contact Us

  |  

FAQ

CAN'T FIND WHAT YOU'RE LOOKING FOR? CLICK HERE!!!